A Conversation for Reading the Guide

Tachyons

Post 1

nessus

I have heard a thoery about tachyons. It states that as a tachyon gains energy it slows down (does this mean at the C it has infinite energy) and inifinite speed it has no energy. What happens if a tachyon enters a gravity well does it?, A- Speed up by falling into the gravity well losing energy(how is this energy lost?smiley - headhurts e.g. Electomagnetic Radiation.) B-Slow down by falling into the gravity well (Does it gain this energy from the gravity well).
When the tachyon leaves the gravity well, does the process go into reverse ?


Tachyons

Post 2

Vip

A148907 may be a better place for answers. People tend to look there first.

Just a thought.

VIP


Tachyons

Post 3

nessus

thanks


Tachyons

Post 4

Vip

Hope it gets some replies!

VIPx


Tachyons

Post 5

JEROS

Ok I'm not a physicist, but if the tachyon DOES gain energy as it slows down, that would mean that at a speed of 0 relative to the speed at which the universe is expanding (now confirmed to be doing just that :read Hawking), it would basically have infinite energy as u said. This presents a few posibilities, like it maybe turns into a white hole(one the blazes stuff and energy OUT not IN), or a sun, coz we know that energy CAN also be made into mass.

at infinite speed it should the have energy=0, or maybe we should just apply Einstein and call it at LIGHT speed to have energy=0. Which is also in total conflict with the very same Einsteins theory:D. So what we have here looks like a paradox to me unless u find a REAL physicist who can teel you that im wrong.

as for what happens when it happens upona black hole, your guess is as good as mine:D

JEROS (in case u dont see my name on top:D


Tachyons

Post 6

b9nr515

At the speed of light wouldn't the tachyone have kenetic energy? And at no speed in what form could it hold the energy?


Tachyons

Post 7

Bluto

A Tachyon is a theoretical particle that can only travel faster than the speed of light c. Any particle would require infinite energy to travel AT the speed of light so yes as a Tachyon slow's down, it would gain energy. To slow down below the speed of light it would require greater than infinity amounts of energy.

Note the use of the word Theoretical - Tachyons have never been detected outside of the Star Trek universe.


Tachyons

Post 8

b9nr515

How, praytell, did the particle get to the speed of light?


Tachyons

Post 9

Bluto

The theory is that the particles would have always been travelling at greater than the speed of light - Probably produced in the big bang or in Stars. I re-itterate though - there is no evidence for the existence of Tachyons and the idea of how to detect them would be mind boggling to say the least!


Tachyons

Post 10

Vip

Are they sort of the opposite to an Einstein universe- here we need huge amounts of energy to approach the speed of light, in that one they need huge amounts to slow down enough to approach it (from the other side, as it were)? Or have I got myself muddled with something else?


Tachyons

Post 11

b9nr515

Einstine eh, traveling at such a speed past the speed of light wouldn't that turn them into energy themselves?


Tachyons

Post 12

Vip

Why? E=mc(2) doesn't have to apply as it's not in this universe and doesn't have to be goverened by our laws. But why would it want to turn to energy?


Tachyons

Post 13

b9nr515

But wouldn't being energy be fun? If it's not in this universe, what universe is it in?


Tachyons

Post 14

NPY

wel, you guys have brought up some interesting stuff.

how bout this - if tachyons only exist in star trek, maybe star trek has a few answers. Like they've loads of episodes in parallel universes, so what if there's something in that??

Whatr if tachyons originate in these parallel universes and the enterprise can tap into them?? How about in this universe the laws of physics are different to in ouyr own and this allows the tachyons to have the streange energy/speed relationship??


Tachyons

Post 15

A.Dent ....in time

Just passing smiley - smiley

The possibility of tachyons. When Albert Einstein proposed his Special Theory of Relativity in 1905, he conceived of the speed of light c as a limiting velocity such that transmission of energy from point to point in space-time at superluminal velocities is impossible: "velocities greater that that of light," he concludes, "have no possibility of existence."This is because the mass of a particle would become infinitely large as its velocity approaches c. The speed of light was therefore conceived to be an inviolable barrier for particle velocities. In the second half of the century, however, physicists such as Olexa-Myron Bilaniuk, V. K. Deshpande, E. C. George Sudarshan, and Gerald Feinberg realized that Einstein's conclusion was overdrawn. Although his equations prohibited the acceleration of particles traveling at subluminal velocities to or beyond c, they did not preclude the existence of particles whose velocities are always greater than or equal to c. After all, photons and neutrinos both travel with a velocity equal to c without ever having been accelerated from a subluminal speed to luminal velocity. So why could there not exist particles that travel at superluminal velocities without ever having been accelerated from speeds less than or equal to c? In this case the speed of light remains an inviolable barrier, but that does not preclude the existence of particles on the other side of the barrier. Feinberg dubbed such particles tachyons, from taciV (swift), and the experimental search for these exotic entities was on.
And, indeed, if tachyons do exist, they are exotic. Apart from other oddities, the equations for energy and momentum for such particles reveal that tachyons would accelerate as they lose energy. Conversely, whenever energy was imparted to a tachyon, it would decelerate. This leads to one of the most peculiar characteristics of tachyons: their prima facie possession of negative energy. Let an observer at rest in a reference frame S observe a tachyon traveling with a velocity v relative to him. This same particle will travel with a different velocity u relative to another observer in a reference frame S1 which is moving with respect to S with a velocity w. When the product vw exceeds c2, the tachyon will possess negative energy relative to S1. More peculiar still, such particles will seem to travel backward in time. To the observer in S1 the negative-energy particle would appear to be absorbed first and emitted later.
The implications of such behavior were noticed by Richard Tolman as early as 1917 in what has come to be known as Tolman's Paradox, namely, that communication with the past is possible. Let an observer O in a reference frame S send out a burst of infinitely fast tachyons at t1 to an observer O1 in a reference frame S1 which is receding from S at the uniform velocity w. The reception of the tachyon signal in S1 triggers a similar burst of tachyons back to O which travel with an infinite velocity relative to S1. The relativity equations dictate that the second signal arrives in S at a time t0 before the burst of tachyons is sent at t1. But, since the signal from O1 to S was triggered by the signal from O to S1, it follows that the effect (O's reception of O1's signal) precedes the cause (O's sending his signal to O1) in S, or, in other words, tachyons furnish the mechanism for backward causation.
This implication alone was enough to warrant the rejection of the possibility of tachyons in the minds of many physicists Proponents of tachyons felt at first constrained to explain away Tolman's paradox with its attendant backward causation by means of a "reinterpretation principle." "It is precisely by putting together the two quizzical concepts of 'negative- energy' particles traveling backward in time that the resolution of the difficulty is found," stated Bilaniuk and Sudarshan; "A 'negative- energy' particle that has been absorbed first and emitted later is nothing else but a positive-energy particle emitted first and absorbed later, a perfectly normal situation." By interpreting any negative-energy particle moving backward in time as a positive-energy particle moving forward in time, one may thereby eliminate the occurrence of an effect before its cause. In our previous case, for example, O1 will naturally regard the tachyon beam received from S as actually a signal that he is himself sending to S1. O1 and O will regard these beams as spontaneous emissions from their own tachyon transmitters rather than as receptions from another reference frame.
Now, at face value, the reinterpretation principle sounds merely like the endorsement of what can only be characterized as a fantastic delusion. If O's tachyon signal really does trigger O1's transmitter to send a return signal, then it is simply irrelevant whether O or O1 believes that no backward causation has occurred. Perhaps the best face to put on Bilaniuk and Sudarshan's remarks is to interpret them as claiming that the causal relation is itself relative to reference frames; that is to say, there is no absolute causal directionality in the same way that there is no absolute simultaneity according to Special Relativity. The world-line of the tachyon burst simply exists (tenselessly) between space-time points in S and S1, and whether the tachyons are moving from S to S1 or vice versa is observer-dependent, as is also which event is conceived to be the cause and which the effect. Unfortunately, it has been shown that, even on this understanding, backward causation cannot be precluded. More to the point, however, the notion that causal directionality is relative to reference frames seems clearly untenable. In their engaging discussion of a tachyonic antitelephone, Benford, Book, and Newcomb point out that causal directionality is independent of temporal considerations and is therefore not susceptible to arbitrary reinterpretation:
For example, let A be William Shakespeare and B Francis Bacon, and let V1 [the outgoing tachyonic velocity] be negative. If Shakespeare types out Hamlet on his tachyon transmitter, Bacon receives the transmission at some earlier time. But no amount of reinterpretation will make Bacon the author of Hamlet. It is Shakespeare, not Bacon, who exercises control over the content of the message (265)
Thus, "the direction of information transfer is necessarily a relativistic invariant. An author's signature, for example, would always constitute an invariant indication of the source" (loc. cit.). The reinterpretation principle is thus seen to be essentially an exercise in self-delusion: causal directionality is invariant across reference frames, and to interpret events as related otherwise than as they are is only self-deception.
In light of these facts, proponents of tachyons began to reassess whether backward causation was after all so objectionable or paradoxical. Some writers argued that the problem entailed by permitting tachyonic backward causation is fatalism. Feinberg, for example, called this the "most serious qualitative objection" to tachyons; the transmission of signals into the past of a single observer "is in apparent conflict with the natural view that one is free to decide whether or not to carry out an experiment up until the time that one actually does so." The objection seems to be that one could, for example, call oneself in the past on a tachyonic antitelephone and then, after receiving the call, decide not to place it after all. Our discussion of theological fatalism, however, makes the flaw in the reasoning clear: the fact that one has received a call from oneself entails not that one is not free to refrain from placing the call, but only that one will not in fact refrain from placing it. If one were to refrain from placing the call, then one would not have received it in the first place. Thus, no fatalistic paradox is generated by the existence of negative-energy tachyons.
But, although objections to tachyons based on fatalism are unimpressive, a more substantive objection appears to arise when one considers cases in which tachyonic backward causation would entail the existence of what Paul Fitzgerald has called a "logically pernicious self-inhibitor" ("Retrocausality," 534/5). Benford, Book, and Newcomb invite us, for example, to envisage a situation in which observers A and B enter into the following agreement : A will send at 3:00 a tachyonic message to reach B at 2:00 if and only if he does not receive a message from B at 1:00. B will send at 2:00 a message to reach A at 1:00 if and only if he receives a message from A at 2:00. Therefore, the exchange of messages takes place if and only if it does not take place. They conclude that "Unless some truly radical solution is found to this paradox, we must conclude that tachyon experiments [such as those being currently carried out] can only yield negative results" (265). John Earman points out that such paradoxes do not depend on human agency, but may be constructed solely with machines. Thus, the reinterpretation principle is irrelevant. A contradiction is generated by asking whether a certain event occurs; we find that it occurs if and only if it does not occur. Although the tachyon event might be interpreted differently by different observers, this difference is totally irrelevant to the contradictory nature of the conclusion.
Now, it is not the existence of tachyons as such, admits Earman, that entails the possibility of a logically pernicious self-inhibitor; rather it is the whole situation which is impossible, and this includes assumptions concerning the possibility of controlling tachyon beams, of detecting them, and so forth. By giving up one or some of these other assumptions, one may impose consistency conditions on hypothetical cases so that the paradox cannot arise. Thus, Fitzgerald maintains that we must conclude only that tachyons cannot be controlled in all ways required for the self-inhibitor to function. When asked why such machines fail, he responds that it may be either for empirical reasons involving constructibility or controllability or owing to a fortuitous set of accidents each time one tries to experiment. The difficulty with the attempt to impose consistency conditions based on considerations of constructibility and controllability, however, Earman explains, is that we have good reason to believe that such devices are possible. The assertion that such experiments cannot be carried out is, therefore, "brazen," since the experiments involve "only operations which we know to be possible in our world." Since such devices as are required for these experiments are apparently nomologically possible, it follows that tachyons are nomologically impossible and therefore do not exist. The threat of fortuitous accidents' preventing such experimentation seems utterly implausible, Fitzgerald himself confesses, for we should then have to posit a lawlike regularity of accidents to prevent the functioning of a machine which should be constructible if tachyons exist ("Tachyons," 428). Hence, the conclusion of the foregoing analysis would seem to be that, given the nomological possibility of tachyon emitters and detectors, one cannot avoid the paradoxes by denying assumptions concerning such devices, but is led instead to denying the possibility of the existence of tachyons. Although this reasoning has, to my knowledge, gone unchallenged in the tachyon literature, there is, within the body of literature on the possibility of time travel, a significant challenge to the modal validity of inferring that tachyons are impossible from the nomological possibility of such devices, a challenge akin to the argument against theological fatalism. Let us therefore turn to that discussion.


Tachyons

Post 16

A.Dent ....in time

Or (yes) you are correct nussus


Tachyons

Post 17

b9nr515

That was a little long winded for just a yes.


Tachyons

Post 18

A.Dent ....in time

Give a man a fish, and he will feed himself for a day
Teach him to fish and he will feed himself for a liftime.


Tachyons

Post 19

b9nr515

Tell a child they can and they will do it.
Tell a child why they can, and they'll probably do it anyway.


Tachyons

Post 20

seldon

Give a man a compilation tape, and he will dance for a night,
Teach a man to scratch, and he'll be dancing for generations.


Key: Complain about this post