Bigger and Bigger Infinities

2 Conversations


It's a commonly held belief that infinity is a pretty weird concept, mixed up with mysticism and staring up into the night sky until the early hours of the morning. This entry is not about that sort of infinity. It is about the idea of a set of things that never ends, that no matter how many of them you count, there's always going to be more you've not looked at yet. This kind of infinity (the mathematical kind) is a lot easier to get a hold on than the vague stargazing kind, and allows us to show some surprising things about infinity, in particular that there are different infinities. There are infinities that really are bigger than other infinities, despite the fact that they all 'go on forever'. The Hitchhiker's Guide to the Galaxy has this to say about the word 'Infinite':


"Bigger than the biggest thing ever and then some. Much bigger than that in fact, really amazingly immense, a totally stunning size, real 'wow, that's big' time. Infinity is just so big that by comparison, bigness itself looks really titchy. Gigantic multiplied by colossal multiplied by staggeringly huge is the sort of concept we're trying to get across here."

Even this doesn't really get across the difference between the finite and the infinite. You have to hijack the word 'bigger' and fly it to places it never thought it would go to talk about the difference between finite and infinite. To talk about how much more enormous the bigger infinities are than the 'smaller' infinities requires the same sort of terrorist activities against common sense definitions of size.

Warning


This entry is quite technical. In the course of it, the existence of bigger infinities is proved. This is, unavoidably, going to be pretty hard. However, no prior knowledge is assumed, and terms used are defined either in the main text or in footnotes at the point the term is first used. It might be an idea to read the definitions footnotes first and refer back to them if needed. Those uncomfortable with maths are probably better skipping to the last paragraph, and just letting the weirdness wash over them.


This entry assumes you believe in the existence of N, the set of all natural numbers, {0,1,2,3,...}1. So how many elements2 does N have? Clearly it's not any finite number of elements, so it must be (by definition) infinite. We3 write |X| for the 'size' of any set X. If X is finite, with (say) 42 elements, we would say |X| = 42, for infinite sets we haven't yet given these 'sizes'4 names, so we just write |N| for the size of N. Now the question is, are there any sets X which have strictly 'more' elements than N? I.e. is there some X such that |X| > |N|?5

More?


Well first we need to say what we really mean by 'more'. We need to do this in a way such that we don't need to count the elements of the sets (which is somewhat difficult for infinite things). To say that X has less than or an equal size to Y (i.e. |X| ≤ |Y|), we can try pairing up each element of X with an element of Y. If we run out of elements of X before we run out of elements of Y, then Y has more elements, pretty obviously. To formalise this, we need a function6 f taking elements of X to elements of Y, which is 'one-to-one', meaning that for a and b different elements of X, they will get sent to different elements of Y by f (f(a) is different from f(b)). Here we are pairing up each a in X with its f(a) in Y, and if we can do that for all the a in X, then we must run out of elements of X before we run out of elements of Y. We need f to be one-to-one, else we would be trying to pair more than one element of X with an element of Y. So to summarise, we say '|X| ≤ |Y|' when we have a one-to-one function f (say) from X to Y.


So that's what 'more' means, defined in a way that doesn't require we count the things. If we have both |X| ≤ |Y| and |Y| ≤ |X| then we can say |X| = |Y|7.


All this is pretty obvious for finite sets (once you've disentangled all that stuff about functions). What is maybe less obvious is that for infinite sets, you can have such a function f (from N to N say) which is one-to-one, but not onto8. For example, if the function f just doubles a number, so for the first few terms, this is what f does:

1goes to2
2goes to4
3goes to6
4goes to8
5goes to10
.........

It's pretty easy to see that if a is different from b, then 2*a is different from 2*b, so f(a) is different from f(b). I.e. f is one-to-one. But (for example) nothing goes to 3, so f is not onto. This sort of thing cannot happen with finite sets. For more fun along these lines, look up Hilbert's Hotel. Note to Editor, last I heard someone was planning to finish this entry off and submit it to Peer Review, but thats not happened yet

Anyway, back to the Plot


Next we define a way to get a new set from one we are given, and show that the new set is really bigger than the old one:


For a set X, the power set of X (written 'P(X)') is defined to be the set of all subsets9 of X. So if X were the three element set {burger, chocolate, doughnut}, then P(X) is the set containing all the subsets of X. I.e.

P(X) = { {burger, chocolate, doughnut}, {burger, chocolate}, {burger, doughnut}, {chocolate, doughnut}, {burger}, {chocolate}, {doughnut}, {} }

Note that last element, the empty set, is a subset of X. It's the subset not containing any elements at all. Also note that although X is a member of P(X) (because the entire set X is, strictly speaking, a subset of X), this doesn't automatically tell us that P(X) has more members than X. burger is not an element of P(X), although {burger} (the set containing only burger) is - there is a difference between these two things. You might want to check that there are no other subsets of X that aren't listed above, drawing some diagrams may help. Note that the order in which we write the elements down doesn't matter.


For finite sets, it's not too hard to show that |P(X)| = 2|X|10 and so |X| < |P(X)|. That's a strict less than - in terms of our functions definition, |X| < |Y| means that there is a one-to-one function from X to Y but there is no possible one-to-one function from Y to X. I.e. Y is just too big to 'fit inside' X. If you think about what this says for finite sets, you'll see that this makes sense as a definition. Ok here's the hard bit: we can show that |X| < |P(X)| for all sets - not just finite ones. Here's the proof, first worked out by Cantor11:

Cantor's Proof


First we can pretty easily show that |X| ≤ |P(X)| by taking the function F(x) = {x} (F is the function (think machine) that on input of an x in X, outputs the subset of X consisting only of x). This is one-to-one because if F(x) = F(y) then {x}={y} (the set containing only x is equal to the set containing only y) so x = y.


We now want to show that there is no possible one-to-one function from P(X) to X. Well we suppose we do have such a function f (right now it seems quite plausible we could have it). Using this f we will get a contradiction, which shows that the f is impossible. For more information on the method of proof by contradiction, see Basic Methods of Mathematical Proof. Here's the clever self-referential bit:


Define a subset S of X by:
S = {a in X such that there is some subset A of X with f(A) = a, and a is not in A}


In other words, S consists of all elements of X that something gets sent to by f and that the thing they get sent to doesn't contain the thing you send. To find out what S is, you go through all the elements a of X, find out if any subset A of X gets sent to a by f, and if also a is not in that A then we know a is a member of S. That may not have helped work out what S is much, but this the crux of the proof. Unfortunately it's a little hard to give examples of what S might look like, because the whole point of this proof is to show that f is impossible, and S is defined in terms of f. We can cheat a bit though: Suppose we take as an example, X is the set consisting of burger, chocolate, and doughnut, so:

X = {burger, chocolate, doughnut}

Suppose f is a function from P(X) to X which does:

{burger, chocolate}goes toburger
{burger, doughnut}goes tochocolate
{doughnut}goes todoughnut

f would have to do something with all the other things in P(X) (subsets of X), but we'll forget about that for the sake of this example. In this case, S = {chocolate}, because the other two are inside the subsets of X that get sent to them by f.


Now S is a subset of X, so it is a member of P(X) (remember P(X) is the set of all subsets of X, and strictly speaking, X is a subset of X), so we can see where it gets sent to under our function f. Let s = f(S). Now the question is wether or not s is in S (it will turn out that both of these are impossible, so we will have to conclude that assuming that f could exist in the first place was wrong). The next two paragraphs are where we find out how the definition of S is so clever. So it would be a good idea to refer back to it when going through them.


Suppose s is in S. Then by the definition of S, there is some subset A of X with f(A) = s, and s is not in A. Well we can find out what that A is. We know that f is one-to-one so f(A) = s = f(S) so A = S, and s is not in A, so s is not in S. But we started this paragraph assuming that s is in S. Contradiction, we can't have s is in S.


Now assume s is not in S. Well there is some subset A of X with f(A) = s (we can take A = S), so for s to not be in S, the last bit "a is not in A" must be false. So "s is not in A" is false. So "s is not in S" is false. So s is in S. Another contradiction.


So the whole thing just doesn't work - when we assumed we had f in the first place, we must have been making a mistake. No such f can exist. So |X| < |P(X)|.

Bigger and Bigger and Bigger Infinities


So we know that |X| < |P(X)| for any set X at all. If we stick N (the natural numbers) in there, we get |N| < |P(N)|. N is an infinite set, so P(N) must be infinite as well, but it's also strictly bigger than N. So it must be a bigger infinity. It turns out that |P(N)| = |R|, the number of points on the real number line. Are there any even bigger infinities, or have we hit the top yet? Well, we can use Cantor's proof again to show that
|P(P(N))| > |P(N)|, and again to show |P(P(P(N)))| > |P(P(N))|, and so on, to get infinitely many bigger and bigger infinities. "How many is 'infinitely many'?" you ask?12 Cantor's proof will get you a different one for each natural number, just by putting that many P's before N. but there are even more than that. There are unimaginably many different sized infinities. For any infinite number you can find more than that many different infinities. It's even provably impossible to form the set of all infinite numbers (which you might want to do in order to try and find out how big it is), it's just 'too big' to even be a set, the axioms of set theory break down with collections of things this big. It's big.

1The curly brackets '{' and '}' are used to denote a set. So we would write the set consisting of burger, chocolate, and doughnut as {burger, chocolate, doughnut}. Sets can also be written in the form of 'all things in some other set which have some property' - so (for example) the set of all even natural numbers would be written {x in N such that x is even}.2An element of a set is simply a member of it. So chocolate is an element of the first set from footnote 1. Two sets are equal if they have the same elements.3'We' as in mathematicians, and now you as well.4The jargon for 'sizes' is 'cardinalities'.5The symbol '>' is read to mean 'is greater than', '≥' to mean 'is greater than or equal to', '<' means 'is less than', and '≤' means 'is less than or equal to'.6A function from a set X to a set Y can be thought of as a machine that takes elements of X in, and gives you back an element of Y. For a function (think machine) f, when you put an element x of X in, the element of Y you get out is called f(x).7It is possible to prove that with one-to-one functions f from X to Y and g from Y to X you can make a one-to-one and onto function h from X to Y (onto means that every element of Y gets outputted by the function (think machine) for some element of X, so there are no elements of Y 'left over' with nothing getting sent to them), which means that h pairs up each element of X with exactly one element of Y, and everything gets paired with something else, so X and Y really must be the same size. This proof however (the Schröder Bernstein theorem), is beyond the scope of this entry.8As also defined in footnote 7, an onto function from X to Y is one such that every element of Y gets outputted by the function. This means that a function that is not onto is one such that some elements of Y get nothing sent to them at all.9A subset of a set X is another set which contains only elements from X - see the section just after this footnote in the main text for examples.10To pick a subset of X, we can go through the elements in turn, deciding if that element is going to be in our subset or not. So if we have |X| elements, we make |X| choices between two options ("is this element in or out?"). The number of ways we can make these choices is then 2|X|.11Georg Ferdinand Ludwig Philipp Cantor 1845-191812Having just proved that there are quite a few of them about, this is a reasonable question to ask.

Bookmark on your Personal Space


Entry

A577875

Infinite Improbability Drive

Infinite Improbability Drive

Read a random Edited Entry


Written and Edited by

Disclaimer

h2g2 is created by h2g2's users, who are members of the public. The views expressed are theirs and unless specifically stated are not those of the Not Panicking Ltd. Unlike Edited Entries, Entries have not been checked by an Editor. If you consider any Entry to be in breach of the site's House Rules, please register a complaint. For any other comments, please visit the Feedback page.

Write an Entry

"The Hitchhiker's Guide to the Galaxy is a wholly remarkable book. It has been compiled and recompiled many times and under many different editorships. It contains contributions from countless numbers of travellers and researchers."

Write an entry
Read more